.m:2

II. Ontological expression

 

3.4  The interpretation of the attributes

     As we have seen, the Spinozian theory of the attribute solves

many problems, but it also raises many others.  One of the most

serious difficulties is that it poses the threat of an idealist or

subjectivist tendency in Spinoza's thought.  We can identify this

problem in the very definition of the attribute: "By attribute I

understand what the intellect perceives of a substance, as

constituting its essence." [Ethics ID4, my emphasis]  One of the

problems which presents itself immediately is that the definition

grants a certain priority to the attribute of thought over the other

attributes: thought is the means of perceiving all the attributes of

substance, including thought itself.  Several examples illustrating

the role of the attribute, such as those in Letter 9 to De Vries, give

an even more problematic explanation.  In this letter Spinoza offers

two examples of how in the attributes "one and the same thing can be

designated by two names."  The first of these two is perhaps the more

problematic: "I say that by Isreal I understand the third patriarch; I

understand the same by Jacob, the name which was given him because he

had seized his brother's heel."  The distinction here is merely

nominal and, more importantly, the difference resides not in the

object perceived but in the perceiving subject, not directly in being

but in the intellect. 

     In Spinoza studies there is a long-standing controversy over the

interpretation of the attributes. (9)  The nucleus of the dispute

involves the position of the attribute with respect to substance on

one side and with respect to the intellect on the other: it is a

question of the priority of ratio essendi and ratio cognoscendi.  The

idealist or subjectivist interpretation defines the attribute

primarily as a form of knowledge and not as a form of being.  Hegel's

presentation in the Science of Logic is the seminal reading in this

tradition. (10)  As we noted above, Hegel conceives of the attribute

as the determination or limitation of substance which is dependent on

the intellect and which "proceeds outside the absolute", [538] that is

"which appears as external and immediate over against substance."

[537]  Martial Gueroult points out that there is a logical

contradiction in this reading which weakens the foundations of

Spinozian ontology: the attributes cannot be dependent on the

intellect because the intellect is a mode of thought and therefore

ontologically posterior to the attributes.  "En effet, si les

attributs r‚sultaient de l'id‚e que l'entendement se fait de la

substance, l'entendement leur serait ant‚rieur, et par cons‚quent

ant‚rieur … l'attribut dont il est le mode, ce qui est absurde." [I,

50]  Hegel himself recognizes this contradiction but seems to credit

it to an error in the Spinozian system rather than to a fault of his

interpretation. [537]  However, the primary issue at stake here, I

would maintain, is not the logical contradiction of the subjectivist

reading, but rather the priority which it grants to the intellect: the

question, I repeat, is the relative import of the ratio essendi and

the ratio cognoscendi in the system as a whole.

     Deleuze provides us with an alternative reading, an objectivist,

ontological interpretation of the attributes.  When Spinoza presents

the attribute as merely a way of knowing or conceiving, such as in

Letter 9, he is giving only a partial or simplified explanation of the

attributes real role. [52]  The attribute does not depend on the

intellect; on the contrary, the intellect plays merely a secondary

role in the functioning of the attributes, as an objective and

invisible agent of representation.  "Tous les attributs formellement

distincts sont rapport‚s par l'entendement … une substance

ontologiquement une.  Mais l'entendement ne fait que reproduire

objectivement la nature des formes qu'il appr‚hende." [56]  In other

words, the relation of the attributes to substance is prior to and

independent of the intellect's apprehension of this relation; the

intellect merely reproduces in objective or cognitive terms the primary

ontological relation.  The ratio essendi is prior to the ratio

cognoscendi.  This objectivist interpretation succeeds in preserving

the ontological integrity of the system and it resolves the

contradiction posed by granting a foundational role to the intellect

in the theory of the attributes.  Nonetheless, we must recognize that

we cannot maintain this thesis without a certain strain.  Let us

return, for example, to the definition of the attributes: "By

attribute I understand what the intellect perceives of a substance, as

constituting its essence." [Ethics ID4, my emphasis]  How can the

objectivist interpretation account for this "quod intellectus de

substantiƒ percipit" without giving a foundational role to the

intellect?  (And we should note that reference to the original Latin

offers us no way out in this dilemma.)  Furthermore, even if we are to

accept the intellect as secondary in the foundation of the attribute,

how are we to understand what Deleuze describes as its "objective

reproduction" of the nature of the forms it apprehends?  This

"reproduction" is certainly a very weak conception of expression. 

     Deleuze does not seem to be disturbed by these problems and he

does not treat this issue in any depth.  What is clear, however, is

the insistence of Deleuze's effort to preserve the ontological

integrity of the system and combat any priority of thought over the

other attributes, even when this effort seems to go against clear

statements in the text.

 

Remark: Althusser reading: speculation and production

     The controversy which poses the alternative between a

subjectivist and an objectivist reading of the attributes is not merely

a philological issue to be debated among Latinists; neither is it an

issue which poses Deleuze's perspective as different merely from the

Hegelian perspective.  Rather, when we broaden our vision we can see

that Deleuze's objectivist reading marks him as largely out of synch

with the intellectual movements of his times, as sustaining a

precariously minoritarian theoretical position.  The intellectual

hegemony in 1960s France of the "masters of suspicion", the partisans

of the trilogy Marx-Nietzsche-Freud, (11) while to an extent anti-

Hegelian, have to be counted nonetheless (if we can allow ourselves a

transposition to the terrain of the Spinozian controversy) on the side

of a subjectivist reading of the attributes.  The various "mots

d'ordre" which spring up from different camps throughout the French

intellectual scene in this period all insist on the foundational role

of the intellect, of the ratio cognoscendi: consider, for example, the

importance of the widely diffuse discourse on "vision", on the seen

and the non-seen, or rather the focus on "interpretation" as a

privileged field of investigation.  Deleuze's proposition of an

objectivist ontological speculation in Spinoza runs counter to this

entire stream of thought; the general trend, in fact, seems to

constitute a forceful attack on Deleuze's position.

     So as not to fall into abstract generalization, let us briefly

investigate Althusser's reading of Marx as an example, perhaps not a

representative example but certainly an influential one.  One element

that Althusser wants to bring into focus, and to bring into question,

is the act of reading itself: reading Marx's Capital, reading the

classical economists, reading capitalist society.  Althusser wants us

to find in Marx a revolution in the theory of knowledge: "il faut

totalement remanier l'id‚e qu'on se fait de la connaissance,

abandonner le mythe sp‚culaire de la vision, et de la lecture

imm‚diates, et concevoir la connaissance comme production." [Lire le

Capital 23]  We can distinguish two elements in Althusser's effort to

conceive of knowledge as a production.  First, we must grasp that

there is a distinction between the object of knowledge and the real

object -- or, to follow Althusser in a Spinozian example, there is a

distinction between the idea of a circle and a really existing circle.

[46 ff.]  As a second step, however, we must recognize that the

importance of this distinction lies in the fact that the two domains

exist under different conditions: while the real object is given, the

thought object is produced in a specific relation to reality.  "Qu'il

existe entre la pens‚e-du-r‚el et ce r‚el un rapport, cela ne fait

aucun doute, mais c'est un rapport de connaissance ...." [107] 

Althusser's insistence on the centrality of ratio cognoscendi is a

characteristic common to all phenomenological speculation.  Before we

can consider real things in themselves, according to phenomenologists,

we must consider how these things are presented to our consciousness,

to our intellect.  This is where the Spinozian attribute reappears at

the heart of the discussion: quod intellectus de substantiƒ percipit. 

Althusser's strategy of reading, along with phenomenological

speculation in general, coincides perfectly with a subjectivist

interpretation of the attribute.  Subjectivist reading puts an end to

the myth of pure speculation, of a "specular" speculation: there is no

innocent or objective reading of the world, of society, of political

economy.

     At first sight, Althusser's critique, which in this respect is

representative of a general intellectual movement, seems to fall

directly and heavily on Deleuze's objectivist reading of the

attributes.  Deleuze gives the intellect precisely the "specular" role

which Althusser denounces: "l'entendement ne fait que reproduire

objectivement la nature des formes qu'il appr‚hende." [56]  How can

Deleuze possibly maintain the theory of a specular, objective

intellect?  How, when the entire French philosophical community is

focusing on the productive nature of knowledge, can Deleuze relegate

the apprehension of the intellect to a reproductive role?  We are

certainly faced with conflicting positions here.  Deleuze's philosophy

is not a phenomenology.  However, when we examine the matter closely,

we find that in certain respects the Althusserian critique does not in

fact directly address Deleuze's argument.  First of all, Deleuze is

not ignoring the centrality of production; rather, he gives the

functioning of the intellect a reproductive role in the theory of the

attribute, because the primary production is elsewhere.  We have

emphasized throughout our reading of Deleuze's various works that his

ontology is founded on the conception that being is a productive

dynamic: in the Bergson study we related this conception to the causal

discourse of the Scholastics and in Spinoza we can trace it to

Renaissance naturalism.  We could summarize Deleuze's ontology in

precisely these terms: being is production in direct, immediate and

absolutely positive terms.  Every discussion of causality and

difference is based on this foundation.  With this in mind, we can

interpret Deleuze's position on the reproductive role of the intellect

as principally an affirmation of the productive role of being.  Thus,

we can hazard a preliminary Deleuzian response to our first

Althusserian critique: bringing cognitive production to center stage

in philosophy masks the fundamental productive dynamic of being which

is really antecedent to the intellect, in logical and ontological

terms. 

     This first response, however, can only serve partially to deflect

the critique, not answer it.  We can approach a more adequate

explanation of Deleuze's position if we bring into question the

domains of knowledge.  While Deleuze's speculation does claim an

objective representation, it applies merely to a very specific domain. 

Society, capital and its economy are not appropriate objects of

speculation; rather, in Deleuze, speculation is brought to bear

exclusively on ontological issues and, as we have insisted at length,

it arrives at very few and very simple ontological principles. 

Against a phenomenological speculation, Deleuze poses a purely

ontological speculation.  What would it mean to conceive of this

ontological speculation as production?  We would have to say, in line

with a subjectivist ontology, that singularity, univocity and power

are not principles of being (as real objects), but rather they are

products of our intellectual activity (as objects of our knowledge). 

In other words, we would have to say that they are not actually

principles of being, but rather "quod intellectus de substantiƒ

percipit".  This sujectivization of being would undermine the

ontological foundation of all of Spinoza's thought.  Deleuze, then,

tries to preserve the specificity of ontology within its specific

domain.  What lies outside of the realm of ontological speculation is

treated by Deleuze in empirical terms: it is the foundation of

Deleuze's conception of practice.

     This second Deleuzian response, however, is still open to a

further Althusserian critique.  The recognition of the production

involved in knowledge and its distinction from reality, according to

Althusser, is defining factor of all materialism: "si on le respect

pas, on tombe immanquablement soit dans l'id‚alisme sp‚culatif soit

dans l'id‚alisme empiriste." [107]  Althusser's materialist and

phenomenological speculation is precisely what allows him to propose

his famous concept of practice within theory, "la th‚orie de la

pratique th‚orique."  Deleuze, then, appears as an idealist on both

sides of this practico-theoretical synthesis: a speculative idealist

and an empirical idealist held loosely together in one philosophy. 

Clearly, Deleuze's conception of practice does not escape Althusser's

indictment: "il suffit de prononcer le mot de pratique, qui pris en

son acception id‚ologique (id‚aliste ou empiriste) n'est que l'image

en miroir, le contre-connotation de la th‚orie (le couple de

®contraires¯ pratique et th‚orie composant les deux termes d'un champ

sp‚culaire), pour d‚celer le jeu de mots que en est le siŠge." [69] 

Deleuze's practice, which pretends to be autonomous, is merely the

compliant specular counterpart to objectivist and idealist speculation

in a fraudulent word game.  Finally, drawing on Althusser's favorite

text, the Theses on Feuerbach, we have to level the accusation that

Deleuze's philosophy can have no practical power; it can merely

attempt to think the world, not change it.  Now, with the critique of

practice, we have touched the heart of the matter, but we do not yet

have control of the terms to investigate it further.  We need, first,

to follow Deleuze's elaboration of the constitutive power of practice

in Spinoza's thought.  Althusser's challenge, though, can serve for

the present as a critical axis to orient our discussion.

 

3.5  Combatting the privileges of thought: Spinoza's parallelisms

     We must return now to consider in greater depth Deleuze's

treatment of the attributes.  Deleuze develops his idea of the

equality of the attributes into a theory of ontological parallelism.

(12)  We should note that the idea of a parallelism of the attributes

does not constitute another principle of being; rather it is simply a

logical extension or development of the idea of the univocity of

being.  If being is always and everywhere said in the same way, then

the attributes must be equal expressions.  In other words, if viewed

from above univocity appears as the absolute uniformity of the whole,

then viewed from below it appears as the equal participation of all

the constituent parts.  We can identify three elements which

constitute Deleuze's theory of ontological parallelism: autonomy,

equality and unity.  The autonomy of the attributes should be

understood foremost as a rejection of the Cartesian conception of the

primacy of the mind over the body.  Spinoza claims, in opposition to

Descartes, that the mind neither controls nor suffers from the body,

and similarly the body neither controls nor suffers from the mind. 

There is a real separation between the attributes.  Spinoza conceives

the mind, then, as a "spiritual automaton" [TdIE 85] because in

thinking the mind obeys only the laws of thought. [cf. Deleuze 126] 

The same, of course, must be said of the body: that is, the body is a

corporeal automaton because in movement and rest the body obeys only

the laws of extension.  This conception of the autonomy of the

attributes rests on one of the principles of efficient causality: in as

much as two things are different, one cannot be the cause of the

other. [cf. IP3]  The attributes, then, constitute independent series

of cause and effect.

     The proposition of parallelism, however, goes beyond a mere

separation between the attributes.  "The order and connection of ideas

is the same as the order and connection of things." [IIP7]  Spinoza's

proposition claims not only that the attributes are autonomous but

also that they are organized in a parallel order.  "En effet,

l'identit‚ de connexion ne signifie pas seulement une autonomie des

s‚ries correspondantes, mais une isonomie, c'est-…-dire une ‚galit‚ de

principe entre s‚ries autonomes ou ind‚pendantes." [95]  A second

component of parallelism, then, is the establishment of an equality of

principle among all the attributes, specifically between the two

attributes accessible to us, thought and extension.  This is the

complete rejection of the Cartesian position: not only is the body

formally independent of the mind, but it is also equal to the mind in

principle.  We must understand equality of principle here in terms of

ontological participation.  The body and the mind both participate in

being in autonomous but equal ways.  Once again, this proposition

follows directly from the principle of univocity: corporeality and

thought are equal expressions of being, said in the same voice.

     We can already recognize that equality does not suffice to

explain ontological parallelism: the different attributes are not only

equal expressions of being they are, in a certain sense, the same

expression. In other words, the modes of each attribute are the same

from the point of view of substance.  "Dieu produit en mˆme temps dans

tous les attributs: il produit dans le mˆme ordre, il y a donc

correspondance entre modes d'attributs diff‚rents.  Mais, parce que

ces attributs sont r‚ellement distincts, cette correspondance ou

identit‚ d'ordre exclut toute action causale des uns sur les autres. 

Parce que ces attributs sont tous ‚gaux, il y a identit‚ de connexion

entre ces modes qui diff‚rent par l'attribut.  Parce que ces attributs

constituent une seule et mˆme substance, ces modes qui diffŠrent par

l'attribut forment une seule et mˆme modification." [97]  The

substantial modification (modificatio) is the unity of modes which are

produced in parallel in the different attributes by a single affection

of substance.  The concept of the modification itself is the

demonstration of what Deleuze's calls the ontological parallelism: the

modes produced autonomously and equally in the different attributes

appear as a unity from the point of view of substance in the form of

the substantial modification.  In Deleuze's interpretation this theory

of Spinozian parallelism functions not so much as an analysis of the

organization of being, (13) but rather as a central lesson for

speculation, one which will guide us throughout our study of the

Ethics: every proposition we affirm with regard to one of the

attributes must be affirmed equally with regard to the other

attribute.  In other words, each time we recognize an aspect of the

structure or function of the mind we must ask ourselves how we can

recognize a parallel structure or function of the body, and vice

versa.  (For example, if we are to affirm a certain nature of a true

idea of the mind, we must also affirm a parallel nature of a true act

of the body.) (14)

     Deleuze's reading of ontological parallelism is an original

interpretation in Spinoza studies.  The beautiful simplicity of it

consists in the fact that it follows very directly from the principle

of univocity.  If being is expressed always and everywhere in the same

voice, then all its attributes must be structured as parallel

expressions; the substantial unity of the modification, which straddles

the different attributes, testifies to the univocity of being. 

Further, the difficulties which we focused on above regarding the

priority of thought in the foundation of the attribute seem to be

resolved (or at least left behind) by the theory of the equality and

ontological parallelism of the attributes.  We should recognize,

nonetheless, that while Deleuze's interpretation fits very well with

the general spirit of Spinoza's ontological system, it does not agree

with Spinoza's actual statement in Proposition 7: "The order and

connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of

things." [IIP7]  Deleuze recognizes that here Spinoza is not proposing

an ontological parallelism but rather an epistemological parallelism.

[99]  This parallelism is not established equally among the various

attributes, but rather it focuses primarily on the attribute of

thought, establishing the relationship between an idea and its

"object" [res ideata, objectum ideae].  The problem is posed most

clearly in the corollary of this proposition: "God's actual power of

thinking is equal to his actual power of acting." [P7C]  To appreciate

the depth of this problem, we must keep in mind that "action" in

Spinoza's terminology does not refer only to the movement and rest of

the body, but equally to all the attributes. [See for example IIID3] 

This formula of P7C, then, is proposing an equality, but not the

equality of the mind and the body; on the contrary, the essence of

thought (the power of thinking) is equated to the essence of being

(the power of acting).  Therefore, we are thrown back on the same

problematic terrain of the subjectivist interpretation of the

attribute.

     Deleuze certainly recognizes this as a serious problem.  Once

again we are confronted by what seems to be a Spinozian tendency to

privilege thought over the other attributes.  The theory of

epistemological parallelism, Deleuze claims, "nous force … conf‚rer …

l'attribut pens‚e un singulier privilŠge: cet attribut doit contenir

autant d'id‚es irr‚ducibles qu'il y a de modes d'attributs diff‚rents,

bien plus, autant d'id‚es qu'il y a d'attributs.  Ce privilŠge

apparaŒt en contradiction flagrante avec toutes les exigences du

parall‚lisme ontologique." [100]  The privilege which seems to be

accorded to thought here goes against the general design of the

ontological system.  In a first attempt to resolve this problem,

Deleuze explains that in the scholium to this proposition Spinoza

proceeds from the epistemological parallelism to the ontological

parallelism, generalizing the case of thought (of the idea and its

object) to all of the attributes.  In this way, Deleuze proposes

epistemological parallelism as secondary, as merely a "detour" [99]

for reaching ontological parallelism, the more profound theory.  This

reading, however, is not very well substantiated in the text.  The

scholium is somewhat suggestive of ontological parallelism but

certainly does not state it clearly; the most suggestive supporting

statement, in fact, is very weak: "I understand the same concerning

the other attributes." [IIP7S]  I did not think that this difficulty

should draw into question Deleuze's proposal of an ontological

parallelism: indeed there is sufficient evidence elsewhere in

Spinoza's work to support this thesis.  The task here is to find a way

to reconcile the two parallelisms so that they do not contradict one

another: or better, to discover a way of avoiding the epistemological

parallelism altogether.

     Deleuze embarks, then, on a more involved discussion in order to

address this task.  The immediate object of this discussion is to

rework the interpretation of the epistemological parallelism proposed

in IIP7.  The fundamental goal, though, which we should keep in mind

through this complex argument, is to combat the privileges of thought

and thereby preserve the ontological foundation of the philosophical

framework.  We must be careful, Deleuze begins, not to confuse the

attributes of being with the powers of being: "la distinction des

puissances et des attributs a une importance essentielle dans le

spinozisme." [103]  While being has an infinity of attributes, it has

only two powers: the power to exist and act and the power to think and

know. [103]  The first power, the power to exist, is the formal

essence of God.  All the attributes participate equally in this

essence, in the power to exist, as formally distinct expressions. 

This is a restatement of ontological parallelism.  The second power,

then, the power to think, is the objective essence of God.  "L'essence

absolue de Dieu est formelle dans les attributs qui constituent sa

nature, objective dans l'id‚e qui repr‚sente n‚cessairement cette

nature." [105]  The same attributes which are distinguished formally

in God are distinguished objectively in the idea of God.  This

formulation of the two powers gives Deleuze the opportunity to combat

the notion of the eminence of thought over the other attributes by

subsuming the epistemological perspective within the ontological. 

"L'attribut pens‚e est … la puissance de penser ce que tous les

attributs (y compris la pens‚e) sont … la puissance d'exister et

d'agir." [107]  This slippage between powers and attributes sets the

terms for a priority between the two powers.  Even though Deleuze

affirmed earlier that the powers are in some sense equal, here we find

that the power to think (objective essence) is dependent on the power

to exist (formal essence): "l'ˆtre objectif ne serait rien s'il

n'avait lui-mˆme un ˆtre formel dans l'attribut pens‚e." [107] 

Deleuze's claim of the priority of the ontological power (the power to

exist) over the epistemological power (the power to think) preserves

the equality among the attributes. 

     Finally, however, there arises yet another case in which it

appears that thought is privileged over the other attributes: in the

mind there are not only ideas which correspond to objects (res

ideata), but there are also ideas of these ideas, and still other

ideas of these ideas of ideas, and so on to infinity.  "D'o— ce

dernier privilŠge de l'attribut pens‚e, qui fonde une capacit‚ de

l'id‚e de se r‚fl‚chir … l'infini.  Il arrive … Spinoza de dire que

l'id‚e de l'id‚e a, avec l'id‚e, le mˆme rapport que l'id‚e avec son

objet." [111]  Before we enter into the details of this argument,

which can easily seem tedious and arcane, we should try to recognize

what is at stake here.  Several commentators have argued that the

problem of the idea of the idea in Spinoza is the problem of

consciousness, or rather the problem of the reflection of the mind. 

Sylvain Zac, for example, poses the concept in this way: "La

conscience est l'id‚e de l'id‚e.  Elle est unie … l'ƒme comme l'ƒme

est unie au corps." [L'id‚e de vie 128, see also 121-8]  While Deleuze

does not pose the issue in these terms, Zac's proposition makes clear

the danger presented for Deleuze by this Spinozian example.  The idea

of the idea, as consciousness, seems to be constructing an interiority

within the mind which, as Zac says, is united with the mind as the

mind is united with the body.  The principal threat of interiority in

this case is the creation of a priority of the mind over the body and

the subsumption of the dynamic of being within a mental dynamic of

reflection.  Therefore, it is quite clear that when Deleuze approaches

this issue his main concern will be to preserve the equality of the

attributes.  The basic problem, then, can be posed quite simply. 

While the idea and its object are conceived under two separate

attributes, the idea of the idea and the idea are both conceived under

the attribute of thought.  What does it mean, then, to say that there

is the same relationship between the idea and the object as there is

between the idea of the idea and the idea?  The claim that the two

cases constitute the same relationship seems to be giving thought the

capacity to subsume the relationship to all of the attributes within

itself: its priority as the attribute of reflection seems to give it

the capacity to reproduce the inter-attribute dynamic completely

within thought itself.  

     Deleuze once again calls on the distinction of powers to address

this difficulty: the two cases cannot be considered the same when

considered from the point of view of attributes, he argues, but only

when considered from the point of view of powers. [110-1]  In other

words, the common relationship in the two cases should be explained by

refering the first term to the formal power and and the second to the

objective power.  The first case is very simple.  The res ideata, as a

mode of being (pertaining to one of the attributes), has a certain

power to exist and it is thus an expression of formal essence.  The

idea of this object, however, refers not to the power to exist but to

the power to think and it is thus an expression of objective essence. 

We can apply this same logic to the second case because an idea is

also a mode of being: a mode of thought, just like a mode of any

attribute, can be refered to the power to exist, as formal essence. 

When an idea is thus conceived we can relate another idea to that

idea, refering now to the power to think: this idea of the idea is an

expression of objective essence.  The common relationship which

Spinoza is refering to, then, is that in each case the two terms refer

to two different powers: the power to exist and the power to think. 

This similarity, however, points to an important difference when we

consider the two cases from the point of view of the attributes.  In

the first, case there is a formal distinction between an idea and its

object because they are modes of different attributes.  In the second

case, though, between the idea of the idea and the idea, there is not

formal distinction because they are both modes of thought.  "ApparaŒt

de ce point de vue l'unit‚ de l'id‚e et de l'id‚e de l'id‚e, en tant

qu'elles sont donn‚es en Dieu avec la mˆme n‚cessit‚, de la mˆme

puissance de penser.  DŠs lors, il n'y a plus qu'une distinction de

raison entre les deux id‚es: l'id‚e de l'id‚e, c'est la forme de

l'id‚e, rapport‚e comme telle … la puissance de penser." [111] 

Deleuze is satisfied with this solution.  He has answered the

intellectualist challenge posed by consciousness by a reference to the

different powers and finally to the ontological hierarchy of

distinctions.  The distinction involved in the dynamic of

consciousness is not the real distinction which founds being, not the

formal distinction which differentiates the attributes, but merely a

conceptual distinction (distinction de raison).  We can pose this

clearly in Bergsonian terms: consciousness does not mark a difference

of nature, but merely a difference of degree.  We have to admit,

nonetheless, that the mind's capacity for reflection (consciousness,

the idea of the idea) gives thought a certain privilege over the other

attributes.  Deleuze's argument, however, drawing on the different

powers and distinctions, attempts to show that this privilege is

ontologically insignificant.

 

Remark: From Forschung to Darstellung

     In the previous section we have analyzed several examples of

Deleuze's effort to preserve the univocity of being on the basis of an

ontological parallelism among the attributes.  The opponent in each

case is an intellectualist reading of Spinoza's epistemology, which at

several points seems to give a real privilege to thought; Deleuze's

strategy, which we have seen already several times in our study, is to

subordinate ratio cognoscendi to ratio essendi.  The Deleuzian

arguments certainly have a very strong foundation in Spinoza's

ontology, in the ontological parallelism of the attributes, but

nonetheless these arguments appear weak when in Spinoza's psychology

and epistemology the problem of privilege continually reappears.  To a

certain extent, the privileges of thought and the problem of the

attributes should be explained as a residue of Cartesianism in

Spinoza's thought, but finally this explanation is not sufficient on

its own.  The theory of the attributes remains a problem in Deleuze's

Spinoza.

     Some readers of Spinoza, who like Deleuze recognize the

centrality of the univocity of being, have tried to resolve this

problem by claiming an evolution in Spinoza's thought: Negri, for

example, argues that the theory of the attributes disappears as

Spinoza proceeds from the pantheistic utopia, which characterizes the

first phase of his thought, to the constitutive disutopia of his

maturity.  The attributes do indeed disappear from the Ethics after

Part II (with only a brief reappearance in Part V) and Negri links

this fact to historical evidence that Spinoza drafted the Ethics

during two distinct periods, from 1661 to 1665 and from 1670 to 1675. 

Negri argues, then, that Spinoza's philosophical transformation

between these two periods precipitates the rejection of the

attributes.  Negri's argument has come under serious critique, but it

clearly points to two issues which, even if we are to question his

explanation, must be addressed: the theory of the attributes is not

easily compatible with Spinoza's mature thought and the attributes are

absent from the later half of the Ethics.

     It seems to me that there is alternative or complementary

explanation to account for the disappearance of the attributes which

is available in Deleuze's work itself.  We could argue, consistently

with Deleuze's interpretation I believe, that thought is privileged in

the theory of the attributes only in limited or accidental terms:

thought is the principle means of human speculation and the theory of

the attributes is linked to a mode of inquiry.  If we imagine that

there is something substantial about the priority of thought over the

other attributes, we are merely confusing the form of our research

with the nature of being.  The attributes appear in the Ethics not as

a form of being, but as a mode of inquiry, as a scientific Forschung. 

Marx makes clear the distinction between Forschung and Darstellung,

between the mode of inquiry and the mode of presentation.  "Of course

the method of presentation must differ in form from that of inquiry. 

The latter has to appropriate the material in detail, to analyse its

different forms of development and to track down their inner

connection.  Only after this work has been done can the real movement

be appropriately presented." [Capital, vol. I, 102]  Therefore, the

two phases of Spinoza's thought, which Negri proposes historically,

can be identified with two moments or approaches in Spinoza's work.

(15)  The Forschung of the Ethics, the moment of speculation, relies

on the theory of the attributes "to track down the inner connection"

of being.  Thought is given a certain priority in this moment, as the

model of our speculation.  "Only after this work has been done," Marx

says, "can the real movement be appropriately presented."  What does

it mean to present appropriately the real movement of being?  Here it

means to present being as it makes itself, in the process of its

constitution: the Spinozian Darstellung refers to practice. When the

moment of research is complete, therefore, after Part II, the

attributes no longer have a role and they drop out of the discussion. 

In other words, as we move forward in Spinoza's system of emendation,

as we shift from speculation to practice, any priority of thought

gradually disappears.  In fact, Deleuze presents a very powerful

argument that Spinoza's theory of practice initially privileges the

attribute of extension: the body is the model of practice.  This seems

to me, then, a consistent Deleuzian explanation of the questions of

priority: in our research of being, in the moment of speculation, the

mind plays the initial role of model; similarly, in Spinoza's

Darstellung, in our practice of being, the body plays a parallel role. 

     How does Spinoza make this shift from Forschung to Darstellung,

from speculation to practice?  Deleuze's work makes cleat that the

hinge or the pivot which articulates these two moments is the thematic

of power.  Spinoza's discussion of power carries the developed

ontological foundation on to the terrain of practice.  It

constitutes, as we claimed earlier, the fundamental passage, the

Nietzschean transmutation: the hour of midnight.  The speculative

Forschung of power merges with its practical Darstellung.  Let us turn

our attention, then, to Spinoza's development of the thematic of

power.