Robert Nau
Professor Emeritus
Fuqua School of Business
Duke University
Research highlights:
My research area lies within
the broad field of rational choice theory, the theory of the expected-utility
maximizing, game-playing, equilbrium-seeking rational economic person. My own
work has primarily focused on foundational issues: primitive assumptions
(axioms) that govern the preferences of rational agents and mathematical
representations of mental processes that might explain such preferences.
Classical work in the field, from the 1920's to 1960's, emphasized the
subjective expected utility model for decisions made under conditions of uncertainty,
in which agents act as if they assign numerical probabilities to events and
numerical utilities to consequences and they make choices so as to maximize the
expected value of their utility. The
expected utility model was formalized by von Neumann and Morgenstern
(1944/1947) with a sweeping scope: "We shall assume that the aim of all
participants in the economic system, consumers as well as entrepreneurs, is
money, or equivalently a single monetary commodity. This is supposed to be
unrestrictedly divisible and substitutable, freely transferable, even in the
quantitative sense, with whatever 'satisfaction' or 'utility' is desired by
each participant." (p. 8) In a situation involving two or more agents,
such as a game or market, they seek an
equilibrium in which each one optimizes his or her expected utility against
the actions of others, ceteris paribus, independently randomizing their choices
for strategic purposes if necessary. The existence of such a solution was
proved by Nash (1951) via a fixed point theorem, and the elegance and power of
this result made it the focal point of game theory as the field developed. A
similarly sweeping formalization of subjective
probability was introduced by Savage (1954), in which agents are assumed to
be able to assign equally precise probabilities to any kinds of events, and it
is the foundation on which "Bayesian" statistics and decision theory
are built.
Beginning in the 1970's this
paradigm was challenged on many fronts as contrary findings emerged from
behavioral experiments and as the preference axioms that support the subjective
expected utility model were reappraised on normative as well as descriptive
grounds. More general models of "non-expected utility preferences"
began to be explored, along with weakenings and strengthenings of solution
concepts for games. However, in nearly all of this newer work, great importance
is still attached to preserving a clean separation between beliefs about events
(represented by probabilities or generalizations thereof) and preferences among
consequences (represented by utilities or generalizations thereof), and the
parameters of utility are still assumed to be measurable with unlimited
precision, regardless of whether the conquences are material goods to be
received or personal experiences to be enjoyed.
Much of my own work has taken
a different approach and has been motivated by analogies with modern physics,
in which variables that were formerly assumed to be measurable on absolute
scales (e.g., space and time) are instead measured relative to the viewpoints
of observers with their own frames of reference, which makes those variables
inseparable to some extent. The economic analog of this phenomenon is that
agents do not in general have observable absolute positions in the space of
material goods and investments and personal well-being that they may possess,
nor are utility functions their natural tools of thought with respect to such
things, let alone functions having values that are interpersonally measurable.
All that can be observed in public are contracts that agents are willing to
sign and relative rates and prices at which they are willing to make exchanges
with each other, which makes it impossible to separate the effects of beliefs
and preferences and endowments when interpreting their behavior. Money plays
(literally) a cardinal role in quantifying the rates of exchange in precise
terms, which is one of its functions. The more we abstract from it, the fuzzier
the numbers become. It may seem that giving a distinguished role to money
rather than utility in the modeling of rational economic behavior would create
problems for decision analysis, which often deals with multiattribute outcomes,
as well as for noncooperative game theory, in which equilibrium probabilities in
randomized strategies are determined from payoff matrices whose units are
utilities. In various papers I have shown that this is not true: there are
natural extensions of these models that do not require the strict separation of
probability from utility. Central to this program is the idea that the
principle of no-arbitrage (avoiding
a sure loss in units of money) is the key axiom that unifies the domains of
rational choice theory that deal with choice under uncertainty: personal
decisions (the 1-body problem), noncooperative games (the problem of 2, 3, 4 .
. . bodies), and investments in markets (the n-body problem for large n).
This approach to modeling
rational choice under uncertainty does not require that the agent only cares
about money or that the only situations that can be analyzed are those whose
primary consequences are monetary. Rather, side bets in units of money which
are conditioned on the agent's own actions can be used as a precise yardstick
for indirectly quantifying her attitude toward risk and her preferences for
other attributes of consequences. The optimal actions for an individual or
equilibrium actions for players in a game are those which do not give rise to
arbitrage in the side bets. To the extent that this story of hypothetical monetary
side bets stretches the imagination, it is an even greater stretch to assume
that agents can know each others' probabilities and utilities or equilibrate on
their beliefs in games and markets with any sort of numerical precision,
particularly when they all may have private information, idiosyncratic
interests, and unobservable background risk.
The fundamental
representation theorems in the three domains (decisions, games, markets) are
all applications of the duality theorem of linear programming, a special case
of the separating hyperplane theorem for convex sets, which has many other
applications in economics. In each domain there is a primal problem whose
variables are actions of the body (moves to be made, offers to bet or trade)
and the objective is for an observer to extract an arbitrage profit, and there
is a corresponding dual problem whose variables are properties of mind
(probabilities, utilities, or combinations thereof) and the objective is to
find values of them that rationalize the actions of the body in the sense of
individual or joint maximization of expected value or expected utility. This
correspondence is well known in subjective probability theory (in de Finetti's
version of it) and in asset pricing theory, but noncooperative game theory, as
it is conventionally presented, takes a very different approach to
characterizing rational behavior. It assumes the expected utility model,
performs some hand-waving about common knowledge of utilities, and then
directly imposes an equilibrium condition (usually Nash equilibrium). What I
have contributed is to show that game theory fits into a continuum with
subjective probability theory and asset pricing theory. Rational behavior in
games can be given a primal definition in terms of avoidance of arbitrage by
the players as a group ("joint coherence"), and application of the
duality theorem of linear programming then leads to correlated equilibrium, first proposed by Robert Aumann (1974),
rather than Nash equilibrium as the fundamental solution concept. The very act
of revealing the rules of the game via conditional side bets on its outcome
(thereby solving the common knowledge problem up front) is equivalent to
asserting that its solution lies in the set of correlated equilibria, and
outcomes that do not have positive probability in some correlated equilibrium
are those which expose the set of players to arbitrage. Moreover, the existence
proof for correlated equilibria does not require the use of a fixed point
theorem. (The obsession with fixed points in economics is unfortunate: they
usually lack a good story about selection and convergence. By comparison, the
no-arbitrage criterion for joint rationality is self-enforcing in the presence
of an alert observer.)
In the most general case, the
units of preference modeling are risk
neutral probabilities, which are the rates at which an agent is publicly
willing to make small side bets on events. This term originated in the finance
literature, where it refers to the probability distribution of a "risk
neutral representative agent" who determines arbitrage-free asset prices.
However, these risk neutral probabilities are not the true subjective
probabilities of a typical real agent, who is risk averse. Rather, they are
interpretable as the product of her subjective probabilities and her
state-dependent marginal utilities for money, with those two psychic dimensions
not being separately measurable, the economic equivalent of space-time. In my
work on this topic I've shown that risk aversion can be modeled without
separating probabilities from utilities by using a generalization of the
Arrow-Pratt risk aversion measure that refers to first and second derivatives
of the risk neutral probabilities rather than first and second derivatives of
utility functions.
The traditional subjective
expected utility model also imposes subtle (and arguably unreasonable)
restrictions on the shapes of indifference curves in payoff space, requiring
the agent to be equally risk averse to all sources of risk. My more general
approach based on derivatives of risk neutral probabilities allows risk
aversion to be source-dependent, which accomodates the phenomenon of ambiguity aversion (also called
"uncertainty aversion") that is illustrated by Daniel Ellsberg's
(1961) famous paradox: most persons would prefer to bet on events whose
probabilities are known (say, the color of a ball drawn from an urn that is
known to hold equal numbers of red and black balls) rather than events whose
probabilities are undetermined (the color of a ball drawn from an urn in which
the numbers are unknown). Ellsberg's subversive idea has inspired the development of many new models in decision theory
over the last few decades.
Some of my other work in the
area of game theory addresses various issues concerning the geometry of the
sets of Nash and correlated equilibria, one of which is illustrated by the
figure above. In the most general case, where risk-averse agents must
reciprocally measure each other's payoffs to establish the rules of the game,
the parameters of correlated equilibrium distributions are risk neutral
probabilities rather than measures of pure belief. Another important analogy
with physics is that the act of measurement tends to perturb whatever is being
measured, resulting in fundamental indeterminacies. This same concept is
relevant to attempts to measure personal probabilities in terms of the rates at
which agents are willing to bet money on events. The very fact that a second
agent may eagerly take the other side of a bet that the first agent has offered
could perturb that agent's beliefs. My work in the area of indeterminate probabilities (the "confidence weighted
probability" model) addresses this phenomenon.
Yet another connection with
physics arises in the modeling of differences in beliefs. Cross-entropy serves as a measure of information gain in a physical
experiment, and this same principle (even the same mathematics) describes the
situation in which a risk averse agent with fixed personal probabilities and no
prior investments comes into contact with a market in which asset prices are
determined from some other probability distribution. In the special case where
the agent has logarithmic utilities, the cross-entropy (KL divergence) between
the two probability distributions is the gain in expected utility that the
agent achieves in transacting with the market until an indifference point is
reached, where her own risk neutral probabilities agree with those that price
the assets. More general utility functions lead to well-known generalizations of
cross-entropy.